Carrying
Out End-of-Life Refusal Orders in a 'Culture of Refusal'
Although
the
following presents the most conservative Catholic view regarding End
Of Life
issues, it does emphasize the central role of "self-determination",
if expressed in timely fashion by a competent person. It also supports
the
concept of "futility", important to both patient and attending
physician. In fact, a physician has a moral and ethical
obligation to
refrain from offering or providing medical care that he or she
considers
futile. One area that bears further comment relates to
"artificial
nutrition", either intravenous or via gastric tube, both of which
mechanisms are associated with signficant medical risks which a
competent
patient not wish to take.
Of course, all of this is moot and often very disruptive to all
involved IF
A PERSON, A FUTURE PATIENT, DOES NOT TAKE THE OPPORTUNITY WHILE STILL
COMPETENT
TO ARTICULATE SELF-DETERMINATION.
GS
==================================================
ZENIT, The world seen from Rome
News Agency
==================================================
Carrying Out End-of-Life Refusal Orders in a 'Culture of Refusal'
2 Criteria to Determine Licitness of Rejecting Life Sustaining Treatment
WASHINGTON, D.C., JULY 4, 2012 (Zenit.org).- Here is a response to a
question
on bioethics, answered by the fellows of the Culture of Life
Foundation.
Q: I am a nurse in a surgical intensive care unit. It is not uncommon
for
family members to announce that their incapacitated loved one would not
want
all of the invasive equipment such as ventilators, feeding tubes,
vasopressive
medications, etc. We are not infrequently directed to remove
tubes and
medications and to start a morphine infusion and to titrate it upward
to make
the patient comfortable. Is it licit for me to carry out these
orders?
E. Christian Brugger responds:
The answer to this question depends on at least two things: first,
whether or
not the directive is expressive of the wishes (i.e, the will) of the
patient;
and second, whether the directive is morally legitimate. Permit me to
consider
both.
The decision whether or not to accept or continue some treatment is
first and
foremost the patient's. The wishes of family members can play an
important role
in assisting patients to make good decisions. But these wishes are
secondary.
This is consistent with the principle of autonomy. Autonomy is simply a
technical term (derived from the Greek words for self, autos, and law,
nomos)
for the truth that God entrusts to each person the moral responsibility
for
self-direction. Autonomy designates both the right and the duty of each
person
to seek out and find the truth and when it's found to adhere to it. The
medical
ethical principle of free and informed consent derives from autonomy.
If a patient has an Advance Directive (AD), health care workers should
appeal
to it for information about patient wishes. Unless there is good reason
to
believe that the information on the AD is false or fraudulent (i.e.,
not
expressive of the rightful will of the patient), or directs some kind
of
immoral behavior (e.g., suicide), medical personnel can carry out the
directives in good faith, including orders for the removal of
life-sustaining
treatments (cf. USCCB, Ethical and Religious Directives for Catholic
Health
Care Services (ERD), 5th ed., no. 59).
If the patient has designated a proxy decision-maker through the
execution of a
Health Care Power of Attorney (HCPoA), then the proxy is legally
authorized to
act as the patient's health care agent to make any necessary care
decisions on
the patient's behalf. The proxy has a grave moral responsibility to
make
decisions according to the will of the patient, and if the patient's
will is
unknown, to make decisions that are in the best interests of the
patient.
If the patient has neither an AD nor a HCPoA, next of kin are often
consulted
in order to clarify the mind of the patient for end-of-life care.
Because
family members sometimes have mixed interests in these end-of-life
decisions,
health care workers should always perform due diligence to ensure that
the oral
directives of family members are consistent with the wishes of the
patient. If,
for example, an elderly widow or widower has three children, the doctor
or
nurse if possible should consult with all three before any
consequential
decisions are executed. Because of the irreversible character of
decisions to
remove life-sustaining treatments, an even greater measure of due
diligence is
required before executing them than before executing decisions to
continue
treatments that are medically indicated to preserve life.
If a health care worker has doubts as to whether some serious directive
stems
from the legitimate will of a patient, he or she should resolve the
doubts
before proceeding with any activity, especially activity that will
result in
the patient's death.
Culture of removal
I said above that rightfully executing medical directives also depends
on
whether the order is morally legitimate. Several factors bear upon the
question
of legitimacy. I will speak about one in particular.
The last 25 years in end-of-life care in the US has witnessed the rise
of an
increasingly rigid refusal mentality toward the use of life-sustaining
procedures, especially for the elderly. It characterizes not only the
culture
of health care institutions and elder-care facilities, but also of
elderly
persons themselves and their families. I don't want to be a burden.
Being
hooked up to tubes is dehumanizing. I would never want to live like
that!,
(meaning on life-support). I'd rather die than sacrifice my
independence. In
our attempt to prize independence and high-functioning, we are
unwittingly
becoming a culture that's intolerant of that stage of radical
dependency that
inevitably accompanies old age.
Catholic teaching holds that a life-sustaining treatment is rightly
refused --
and only rightly refused -- if it's futile (i.e., it does not promise a
reasonable hope of benefit) or it's excessively burdensome (cf. ERD
57).
Otherwise, it should be accepted. Why? For the simple reason that life
is
always good, even when incapacitated. Because of its intrinsic
goodness, the
effort to preserve it ordinarily holds a presumption over letting die.
This is
simply another way of saying that sustaining life, though not always
required,
is never pointless. The proposition that asserts: this or that life is
not
worth living is literally never true. No human life, no matter how
diminished
in its capacities, is without intrinsic worth. So strictly speaking,
every life
at every stage under every condition is worth living.
But morality does not require us in every instance to do everything
possible to
sustain life. The presumption to act on behalf of its preservation (but
never
to act against it) can be overridden when very serious burdens promise
to
accompany its preservation. No one who knows Catholic teaching on
end-of-life
care in the last 60 years can rightly accuse the Church of imposing,
advancing,
or even implicitly holding an unreasonable preservationist
mentality.
Whereas the pendulum in the 1950s-1970s may have tilted excessively in
the
direction of adopting life-preserving measures, no such excess exists
today.
The duty to refuse has become the mantra of the 21stcentury. And health
care
workers must do what they can to resist it.
Given the widespread refusal mentality today and the pressure it places
especially on elderly persons, there is an increasing probability that
refusal
directives, whether given orally or codified onto forms such as Living
Wills
(or the dangerous new document known as the POLST form), will be
wrongly
decided. Patients who have a duty to accept antibiotic infusions, or
intubation
for assisted feeding or respiration, or CPR, or dialysis, precisely
because
those treatments would not be futile and do not pose an excessive
burden, may
be wrongly motivated to direct that they be removed or withheld.
Having said this, I do not think that health care workers are morally
bound to
scrutinize the motives of every patient who directs the refusal of
life-sustaining treatments. This would unnecessarily burden the
delivery of
health care by imposing on physicians, nurses and physician assistants
a task
that at least in some instances could not be carried through to
completion (an
unconscious patient with a refusal order can no longer express his or
her
intentions).
But those who advise and assist patients in completing ADs have the
duty to
facilitate good moral decision making. Patients inclined to refuse
life-support
should only do so for upright reasons (e.g., when proposed treatments
are
disproportionate to the benefits promised). Likewise they should be
encouraged
(without coercion) not to act on disordered motives (e.g., because they
feel
their life has lost its value, because others want them to refuse,
because they
are afraid of being a burden on their caregivers, etc.). Advisers
should, I
believe, inform patients completing AD's of the work of the Patients
Rights
Council.
Finally, immoral orders should not be carried out. In some instances,
assessing
the wrongness of an order is straightforward, for example, the order to
remove
nutrition and hydration from a patient for whom they are necessary to
sustain
life (cf. ERD 58). But some refusal orders are more difficult to
assess.
In principle, any order that directs the withholding or removal of
life-sustaining procedures judged to be ordinary and proportionate is
unethical
and contrary to Catholic teaching (cf. ERDs 56-57). Making this
judgment is not
always so simple. And so, following ERD 59, health care workers may
presume
that refusal orders are rightly decided unless there are good reasons
for concluding
otherwise. If there are good reasons, then health care workers should
undertake
due diligence in order to resolve their doubts before carrying out the
order.